|
80- The
indispensable requirements of the word of God

The indispensable requirements of the word of God
80. In Sacred Scripture are found elements, both implicit
and explicit, which allow a vision of the human being and
the world which has exceptional philosophical density.
Christians have come to an ever deeper awareness of the
wealth to be found in the sacred text. It is there that
we learn that what we experience is not absolute: it is
neither uncreated nor self-generating. God alone is the
Absolute. From the Bible there emerges also a vision of
man as imago Dei. This vision offers indications
regarding man's life, his freedom and the immortality of
the human spirit. Since the created world is not
self-sufficient, every illusion of autonomy which would
deny the essential dependence on God of every
creaturethe human being includedleads to
dramatic
situations which subvert the rational search for the
harmony and the meaning of human life.
The problem of moral
evilthe most tragic of evil's formsis also
addressed in the Bible, which tells us that such evil
stems not from any material deficiency, but is a wound
inflicted by the disordered exercise of human freedom. In
the end, the word of God poses the problem of the meaning
of life and proffers its response in directing the human
being to Jesus Christ, the Incarnate Word of God, who is
the perfect realization of human existence. A reading of
the sacred text would reveal other aspects of this
problem; but what emerges clearly is the rejection of all
forms of relativism, materialism and pantheism.
The fundamental conviction of
the philosophy found in the Bible is that the
world and human life do have a meaning and look towards
their fulfilment, which comes in Jesus Christ. The
mystery of the Incarnation will always remain the central
point of reference for an understanding of the enigma of
human existence, the created world and God himself. The
challenge of this mystery pushes philosophy to its
limits, as reason is summoned to make its own a logic
which brings down the walls within which it risks being
confined. Yet only at this point does the meaning of life
reach its defining moment. The intimate essence of God
and of the human being become intelligible: in the
mystery of the Incarnate Word, human nature and divine
nature are safeguarded in all their autonomy, and at the
same time the unique bond which sets them together in
mutuality without confusion of any kind is revealed.(97)
81. One of the most significant
aspects of our current situation, it should be noted, is
the crisis of meaning. Perspectives on life
and the world, often of a scientific temper, have so
proliferated that we face an increasing fragmentation of
knowledge. This makes the search for meaning difficult
and often fruitless. Indeed, still more dramatically, in
this maelstrom of data and facts in which we live and
which seem to comprise the very fabric of life, many
people wonder whether it still makes sense to ask about
meaning. The array of theories which vie to give an
answer, and the different ways of viewing and of
interpreting the world and human life, serve only to
aggravate this radical doubt, which can easily lead to
scepticism, indifference or to various forms of
nihilism.
In consequence, the human spirit
is often invaded by a kind of ambiguous thinking which
leads it to an ever deepening introversion, locked within
the confines of its own immanence without reference of
any kind to the transcendent. A philosophy which no
longer asks the question of the meaning of life would be
in grave danger of reducing reason to merely accessory
functions, with no real passion for the search for truth.
To be consonant with the word of
God, philosophy needs first of all to recover its
sapiential dimension as a search for the ultimate and
overarching meaning of life. This first requirement is in
fact most helpful in stimulating philosophy to conform to
its proper nature. In doing so, it will be not only the
decisive critical factor which determines the foundations
and limits of the different fields of scientific
learning, but will also take its place as the ultimate
framework of the unity of human knowledge and action,
leading them to converge towards a final goal and
meaning. This sapiential dimension is all the more
necessary today,
because the immense expansion of humanity's technical
capability demands a renewed and sharpened sense of
ultimate values. If this technology is not ordered to
something greater than a merely utilitarian end, then it
could soon prove inhuman and even become potential
destroyer of the human race.(98)
The word of God reveals the
final destiny of men and women and provides a unifying
explanation of all that they do in the world. This is why
it invites philosophy to engage in the search for the
natural foundation of this meaning, which corresponds to
the religious impulse innate in every person. A
philosophy denying the possibility of an ultimate and
overarching meaning would be not only ill-adapted to its
task, but false.
82. Yet this sapiential function
could not be performed by a philosophy which was not
itself a true and authentic knowledge, addressed, that
is, not only to particular and subordinate aspects of
realityfunctional, formal or utilitarianbut
to its total and definitive truth, to the very being of
the object which is known. This prompts a second
requirement: that philosophy verify the human capacity to
know the truth, to come to a knowledge which can reach
objective truth by means of that adaequatio rei et
intellectus to which the Scholastic Doctors referred.(99)
This requirement, proper to faith, was explicitly
reaffirmed by the Second Vatican Council:
Intelligence is not confined to observable data
alone. It can with genuine certitude attain to reality
itself as knowable, though in consequence of sin that
certitude is partially obscured and weakened. (100)
A radically phenomenalist or
relativist philosophy would be ill-adapted to help in the
deeper exploration of the riches found in the word of
God. Sacred Scripture always assumes that the individual,
even if guilty of duplicity and mendacity, can know and
grasp the clear and simple truth. The Bible, and the New
Testament in particular, contains texts and statements
which have a genuinely ontological content. The inspired
authors intended to formulate true statements, capable,
that is, of expressing objective reality. It cannot be
said that the Catholic tradition erred when it took
certain texts of Saint John and Saint Paul to be
statements about the very being of Christ. In seeking to
understand and explain these statements, theology needs
therefore the
contribution of a philosophy which does not disavow the
possibility of a knowledge which is objectively true,
even if not perfect. This applies equally to the
judgements of moral conscience, which Sacred Scripture
considers capable of being objectively true. (101)
83. The two requirements already
stipulated imply a third: the need for a philosophy of
genuinely metaphysical range, capable, that is, of
transcending empirical data in order to attain something
absolute, ultimate and foundational in its search for
truth. This requirement is implicit in sapiential and
analytical knowledge alike; and in particular it is a
requirement for knowing the moral good, which has its
ultimate foundation in the Supreme Good, God himself.
Here I do not mean to speak of metaphysics in the sense
of a specific school or a particular historical current
of thought. I want only to state that reality and truth
do transcend the factual and the empirical, and to
vindicate the human being's capacity to know this
transcendent and metaphysical dimension in a way that is
true and certain, albeit imperfect and analogical. In
this sense, metaphysics should not be seen as an
alternative to anthropology, since it is metaphysics
which makes it possible to ground the concept of personal
dignity in virtue of their spiritual nature. In a special
way, the person constitutes a privileged locus for the
encounter with being, and hence with metaphysical
enquiry.
Wherever men and women discover
a call to the absolute and transcendent, the metaphysical
dimension of reality opens up before them: in truth, in
beauty, in moral values, in other persons, in being
itself, in God. We face a great challenge at the end of
this millennium to move from phenomenon to foundation, a
step as necessary as it is urgent. We cannot stop short
at experience alone; even if experience does reveal the
human being's interiority and spirituality, speculative
thinking must penetrate to the spiritual core and the
ground from which it rises. Therefore, a philosophy which
shuns metaphysics would be radically unsuited to the task
of mediation in the understanding of Revelation.
The word of God refers
constantly to things which transcend human experience and
even human thought; but this mystery could
not be revealed, nor could theology render it in some way
intelligible, (102) were human knowledge limited strictly
to the world of sense experience. Metaphysics thus plays
an essential role of mediation in theological research. A
theology without a metaphysical horizon could not move
beyond an analysis of religious experience, nor would it
allow the intellectus fidei to give a coherent account of
the universal and transcendent value of revealed truth.
If I insist so strongly on the
metaphysical element, it is because I am convinced that
it is the path to be taken in order to move beyond the
crisis pervading large sectors of philosophy at the
moment, and thus to correct certain mistaken modes of
behaviour now widespread in our society.
84. The importance of
metaphysics becomes still more evident if we consider
current developments in hermeneutics and the analysis of
language. The results of such studies can be very helpful
for the understanding of faith, since they bring to light
the structure of our thought and speech and the meaning
which language bears. However, some scholars working in
these fields tend to stop short at the question of how
reality is understood and expressed, without going
further to see whether reason can discover its essence.
How can we fail to see in such a frame of mind the
confirmation of our present crisis of confidence in the
powers of reason? When, on the basis of preconceived
assumptions, these positions tend to obscure the contents
of faith or to deny their universal validity, then not
only do they abase reason but in so doing they also
disqualify themselves. Faith clearly presupposes that
human language is capable of expressing divine and
transcendent reality in a universal
wayanalogically, it is true, but no less
meaningfully for that. (103) Were this not so, the word
of God, which is always a divine word in human language,
would not be capable of saying anything about God. The
interpretation of this word cannot merely keep referring
us to one interpretation after another, without ever
leading us to a statement which is simply true; otherwise
there would be no Revelation of God, but only the
expression of human notions about God and about what God
presumably thinks of us.
85. I am well aware that these
requirements which the word of God imposes upon
philosophy may seem daunting to many people involved in
philosophical research today. Yet this is why, taking up
what has been taught repeatedly by the Popes for several
generations and reaffirmed by the Second Vatican Council
itself, I wish to reaffirm strongly the conviction that
the human being can come to a unified and organic vision
of knowledge. This is one of the tasks which Christian
thought will have to take up through the next millennium
of the Christian era. The segmentation of knowledge, with
its splintered approach to truth and consequent
fragmentation of meaning, keeps people today from coming
to an interior unity. How could the Church not be
concerned by this? It is the Gospel which imposes this
sapiential task directly upon her Pastors, and they
cannot shrink from their duty to undertake it.
I believe that those
philosophers who wish to respond today to the demands
which the word of God makes on human thinking should
develop their thought on the basis of these postulates
and in organic continuity with the great tradition which,
beginning with the ancients, passes through the Fathers
of the Church and the masters of Scholasticism and
includes the fundamental achievements of modern and
contemporary thought. If philosophers can take their
place within this tradition and draw their inspiration
from it, they will certainly not fail to respect
philosophy's demand for autonomy.
In the present situation,
therefore, it is most significant that some philosophers
are promoting a recovery of the determining role of this
tradition for a right approach to knowledge. The appeal
to tradition is not a mere remembrance of the past; it
involves rather the recognition of a cultural heritage
which belongs to all of humanity. Indeed it may be said
that it is we who belong to the tradition and that it is
not ours to dispose of at will. Precisely by being rooted
in the tradition will we be able today to develop for the
future an original, new and constructive mode of
thinking. This same appeal is all the more valid for
theology. Not only because theology has the living
Tradition of the Church as its original source, (104) but
also because, in virtue of this, it must be able to
recover both the profound theological tradition of
earlier times and the enduring tradition of that
philosophy which by dint of its authentic wisdom can
transcend the boundaries of space and time.
86. This insistence on the need
for a close relationship of continuity between
contemporary philosophy and the philosophy developed in
the Christian tradition is intended to avert the danger
which lies hidden in some currents of thought which are
especially prevalent today. It is appropriate, I think,
to review them, however briefly, in order to point out
their errors and the consequent risks for philosophical
work.
The first goes by the name of
eclecticism, by which is meant the approach of those who,
in research, teaching and argumentation, even in
theology, tend to use individual ideas drawn from
different philosophies, without concern for their
internal coherence, their place within a system or their
historical context. They therefore run the risk of being
unable to distinguish the part of truth of a given
doctrine from elements of it which may be erroneous or
ill-suited to the task at hand. An extreme form of
eclecticism appears also in the rhetorical misuse of
philosophical terms to which some theologians are given
at times. Such
manipulation does not help the search for truth and does
not train reasonwhether theological or
philosophicalto formulate arguments seriously and
scientifically. The rigorous and far-reaching study of
philosophical doctrines, their particular terminology and
the context in which they arose, helps to overcome the
danger of eclecticism and makes it possible to integrate
them into theological discourse in a way appropriate to
the task.
87. Eclecticism is an error of
method, but lying hidden within it can also be the claims
of historicism. To understand a doctrine from the past
correctly, it is necessary to set it within its proper
historical and cultural context. The fundamental claim of
historicism, however, is that the truth of a philosophy
is determined on the basis of its appropriateness to a
certain period and a certain historical purpose. At least
implicitly, therefore, the enduring validity of truth is
denied. What was true in one period, historicists claim,
may not be true in another. Thus for them the history of
thought becomes little more than an archeological
resource useful for illustrating positions once held, but
for the most part outmoded and meaningless now. On the
contrary, it should not be forgotten that, even if a
formulation is bound in some way by time and culture, the
truth or the error which it expresses can invariably be
identified and evaluated as such despite the distance of
space and time.
In theological enquiry,
historicism tends to appear for the most part under the
guise of modernism. Rightly concerned to make
theological discourse relevant and understandable to our
time, some theologians use only the most recent opinions
and philosophical language, ignoring the critical
evaluation which ought to be made of them in the light of
the tradition. By exchanging relevance for truth, this
form of modernism shows itself incapable of satisfying
the demands of truth to which theology is called to
respond.
88. Another threat to be
reckoned with is scientism. This is the philosophical
notion which refuses to admit the validity of forms of
knowledge other than those of the positive sciences; and
it relegates religious, theological, ethical and
aesthetic knowledge to the realm of mere fantasy. In the
past, the same idea emerged in positivism and
neo-positivism, which considered metaphysical statements
to be meaningless. Critical epistemology has discredited
such a claim, but now we see it revived in the new guise
of scientism, which dismisses values as mere products of
the emotions and rejects the notion of being in order to
clear the way for pure and simple facticity. Science
would thus be poised to dominate all aspects of human
life through technological progress. The undeniable
triumphs of scientific research and contemporary
technology have helped to propagate a scientistic
outlook, which now seems boundless, given its inroads
into different cultures and the radical changes it has
brought.
Regrettably, it must be noted,
scientism consigns all that has to do with the question
of the meaning of life to the realm of the irrational or
imaginary. No less disappointing is the way in which it
approaches the other great problems of philosophy which,
if they are not ignored, are subjected to analyses based
on superficial analogies, lacking all rational
foundation. This leads to the impoverishment of human
thought, which no longer addresses the ultimate problems
which the human being, as the animal rationale, has
pondered constantly from the beginning of time. And since
it leaves no space for the critique offered by ethical
judgement, the scientistic mentality has succeeded in
leading many to think that if something is technically
possible it is therefore morally admissible.
89. No less dangerous is
pragmatism, an attitude of mind which, in making its
choices, precludes theoretical considerations or
judgements based on ethical principles. The practical
consequences of this mode of thinking are significant. In
particular there is growing support for a concept of
democracy which is not grounded upon any reference to
unchanging values: whether or not a line of action is
admissible is decided by the vote of a parliamentary
majority. (105) The consequences of this are clear: in
practice, the great moral decisions of humanity are
subordinated to decisions taken one after another by
institutional agencies. Moreover, anthropology itself is
severely compromised by a one-dimensional vision of the
human being, a vision which excludes the great ethical
dilemmas and the existential analyses of the meaning of
suffering and sacrifice, of life and death.
90. The positions we have
examined lead in turn to a more general conception which
appears today as the common framework of many
philosophies which have rejected the meaningfulness of
being. I am referring to the nihilist interpretation,
which is at once the denial of all foundations and the
negation of all objective truth. Quite apart from the
fact that it conflicts with the demands and the content
of the word of God, nihilism is a denial of the humanity
and of the very identity of the human being. It should
never be forgotten that the neglect of being inevitably
leads to losing touch with objective truth and therefore
with the very ground of human dignity. This in turn makes
it possible to erase from the countenance of man and
woman the marks of their likeness to God, and thus to
lead them little by little either to a destructive will
to power or to a solitude without hope. Once the truth is
denied to human beings, it is pure illusion to try to set
them free. Truth and freedom either go together hand in
hand or together they perish in misery. (106)
91. In discussing these currents
of thought, it has not been my intention to present a
complete picture of the present state of philosophy,
which would, in any case, be difficult to reduce to a
unified vision. And I certainly wish to stress that our
heritage of knowledge and wisdom has indeed been enriched
in different fields. We need only cite logic, the
philosophy of language, epistemology, the philosophy of
nature, anthropology, the more penetrating analysis of
the affective dimensions of knowledge and the existential
approach to the analysis of freedom. Since the last
century, however, the affirmation of the principle of
immanence, central to the rationalist argument, has
provoked a radical requestioning of claims once thought
indisputable. In response, currents of irrationalism
arose, even as the baselessness of the demand that reason
be absolutely self-grounded was being critically
demonstrated.
Our age has been termed by some
thinkers the age of postmodernity. Often used
in very different contexts, the term designates the
emergence of a complex of new factors which, widespread
and powerful as they are, have shown themselves able to
produce important and lasting changes. The term was first
used with reference to aesthetic, social and
technological phenomena. It was then transposed into the
philosophical field, but has remained somewhat ambiguous,
both because judgement on what is called
postmodern is sometimes positive and
sometimes negative, and because there is as yet no
consensus on the delicate question of the demarcation of
the different historical periods. One thing however is
certain: the currents of thought which claim to be
postmodern merit appropriate attention. According to some
of them, the time of certainties is irrevocably past, and
the human being must now learn to live in a horizon of
total absence of meaning, where everything is provisional
and ephemeral. In their destructive critique of every
certitude, several authors have failed to make crucial
distinctions and have called into question the certitudes
of faith.
This nihilism has been justified
in a sense by the terrible experience of evil which has
marked our age. Such a dramatic experience has ensured
the collapse of rationalist optimism, which viewed
history as the triumphant progress of reason, the source
of all happiness and freedom; and now, at the end of this
century, one of our greatest threats is the temptation to
despair.
Even so, it remains true that a
certain positivist cast of mind continues to nurture the
illusion that, thanks to scientific and technical
progress, man and woman may live as a demiurge,
single-handedly and completely taking charge of their
destiny.

|