|
Chapter 4 : 36-48
The Relationship between faith and reason

CHAPTER IV
THE RELATIONSHIP
BETWEEN FAITH AND REASON
Important
moments in the encounter of faith and reason
36. The Acts of the Apostles
provides evidence that Christian proclamation was engaged
from the very first with the philosophical currents of
the time. In Athens, we read, Saint Paul entered into
discussion with certain Epicurean and Stoic
philosophers (17:18); and exegetical analysis of
his speech at the Areopagus has revealed frequent
allusions to popular beliefs deriving for the most part
from Stoicism. This is by no means accidental. If pagans
were to understand them, the first Christians could not
refer only to Moses and the prophets when
they spoke. They had to point as well to natural
knowledge of God and to the voice of conscience in every
human being (cf. Rom 1:19-21; 2:14-15; Acts 14:16-17).
Since in pagan religion this natural knowledge had lapsed
into idolatry (cf. Rom 1:21-32), the Apostle judged it
wiser in his speech to make the link with the thinking of
the philosophers, who had always set in opposition to the
myths and mystery cults notions more respectful of divine
transcendence.
One of the major concerns of
classical philosophy was to purify human notions of God
of mythological elements. We know that Greek religion,
like most cosmic religions, was polytheistic, even to the
point of divinizing natural things and phenomena. Human
attempts to understand the origin of the gods and hence
the origin of the universe find their earliest expression
in poetry; and the theogonies remain the first evidence
of this human search. But it was the task of the fathers
of philosophy to bring to light the link between reason
and religion. As they broadened their view to include
universal principles, they no longer rested content with
the ancient myths, but wanted to provide a rational
foundation for their belief in the divinity. This opened
a path which took its rise from ancient traditions but
allowed a development satisfying the demands of universal
reason. This development sought to
acquire a critical awareness of what they believed in,
and the concept of divinity was the prime beneficiary of
this. Superstitions were recognized for what they were
and religion was, at least in part, purified by rational
analysis. It was on this basis that the Fathers of the
Church entered into fruitful dialogue with ancient
philosophy, which offered new ways of proclaiming and
understanding the God of Jesus Christ.
37. In tracing Christianity's
adoption of philosophy, one should not forget how
cautiously Christians regarded other elements of the
cultural world of paganism, one example of which is
gnosticism. It was easy to confuse
philosophyunderstood as practical wisdom and an
education for lifewith a higher and esoteric kind
of knowledge, reserved to those few who were perfect. It
is surely this kind of esoteric speculation which Saint
Paul has in mind when he puts the Colossians on their
guard: See to it that no-one takes you captive
through philosophy and empty deceit, according to human
tradition, according to the elemental spirits of the
universe and not according to Christ (2:8). The
Apostle's words seem all too pertinent now if we apply
them to the various kinds of esoteric superstition
widespread today, even among some believers who lack a
proper critical sense. Following Saint Paul, other
writers of the early centuries, especially Saint Irenaeus
and Tertullian, sound the alarm when confronted with a
cultural perspective which sought to subordinate the
truth of Revelation to the interpretation of the
philosophers.
38. Christianity's engagement
with philosophy was therefore neither straight-forward
nor immediate. The practice of philosophy and attendance
at philosophical schools seemed to the first Christians
more of a disturbance than an opportunity. For them, the
first and most urgent task was the proclamation of the
Risen Christ by way of a personal encounter which would
bring the listener to conversion of heart and the request
for Baptism. But that does not mean that they ignored the
task of deepening the understanding of faith and its
motivations. Quite the contrary. That is why the
criticism of Celsusthat Christians were
illiterate and uncouth(31)is unfounded
and untrue. Their initial disinterest is to be explained
on other grounds. The encounter with the Gospel offered
such a satisfying answer to the hitherto unresolved
question of life's meaning that delving into the
philosophers seemed to them something remote and in some
ways outmoded.
That seems still more evident
today, if we think of Christianity's contribution to the
affirmation of the right of everyone to have access to
the truth. In dismantling barriers of race, social status
and gender, Christianity proclaimed from the first the
equality of all men and women before God. One prime
implication of this touched the theme of truth. The
elitism which had characterized the ancients' search for
truth was clearly abandoned. Since access to the truth
enables access to God, it must be denied to none. There
are many paths which lead to truth, but since Christian
truth has a salvific value, any one of these paths may be
taken, as long as it leads to the final goal, that is to
the Revelation of Jesus Christ.
A pioneer of positive engagement
with philosophical thinkingalbeit with cautious
discernmentwas Saint Justin. Although he continued
to hold Greek philosophy in high esteem after his
conversion, Justin claimed with power and clarity that he
had found in Christianity the only sure and
profitable philosophy.(32) Similarly, Clement of
Alexandria called the Gospel the true
philosophy,(33) and he understood philosophy, like
the Mosaic Law, as instruction which prepared for
Christian faith (34) and paved the way for the
Gospel.(35) Since philosophy yearns for the wisdom
which consists in rightness of soul and speech and in
purity of life, it is well disposed towards wisdom and
does all it can to acquire it. We call philosophers those
who love the wisdom that is creator and mistress of all
things, that is knowledge of the Son of God.(36)
For Clement, Greek philosophy is not meant in the first
place to bolster and complete Christian truth. Its task
is rather the defence of the faith: The teaching of
the Saviour is perfect in itself and has no need of
support, because it is the strength and the wisdom of
God. Greek philosophy, with its contribution, does not
strengthen truth; but, in rendering the attack of
sophistry impotent and in disarming those who betray
truth and wage war upon it, Greek philosophy is rightly
called the hedge and the protective wall around the
vineyard.(37)
39. It is clear from history,
then, that Christian thinkers were critical in adopting
philosophical thought. Among the early examples of this,
Origen is certainly outstanding. In countering the
attacks launched by the philosopher Celsus, Origen adopts
Platonic philosophy to shape his argument and mount his
reply. Assuming many elements of Platonic thought, he
begins to construct an early form of Christian theology.
The name theology itself, together with the
idea of theology as rational discourse about God, had to
this point been tied to its Greek origins. In
Aristotelian philosophy, for example, the name signified
the noblest part and the true summit of philosophical
discourse. But in the light of Christian Revelation what
had signified a generic doctrine about the gods assumed a
wholly new meaning, signifying now the reflection
undertaken by the believer in order to express the true
doctrine about God. As it developed, this new Christian
thought made use of philosophy, but at the same time
tended to distinguish itself clearly from philosophy.
History shows how Platonic thought, once adopted by
theology, underwent profound changes, especially with
regard to concepts such as the immortality of the soul,
the divinization of man and the origin of evil.
40. In this work of
christianizing Platonic and Neo-Platonic thought, the
Cappadocian Fathers, Dionysius called the Areopagite and
especially Saint Augustine were important. The great
Doctor of the West had come into contact with different
philosophical schools, but all of them left him
disappointed. It was when he encountered the truth of
Christian faith that he found strength to undergo the
radical conversion to which the philosophers he had known
had been powerless to lead him. He himself reveals his
motive: From this time on, I gave my preference to
the Catholic faith. I thought it more modest and not in
the least misleading to be told by the Church to believe
what could not be demonstratedwhether that was
because a demonstration existed but could not be
understood by all or whether the matter was not one open
to rational proofrather than from the Manichees to
have a rash promise of knowledge with mockery of mere
belief, and then afterwards to be ordered to believe many
fabulous and absurd myths impossible to prove
true.(38) Though he accorded the Platonists a place
of privilege, Augustine rebuked them because, knowing the
goal to seek, they had ignored the path which leads to
it: the Word made flesh.(39) The Bishop of Hippo
succeeded in producing the first great synthesis of
philosophy and theology, embracing currents of thought
both Greek and Latin. In him too the great unity of
knowledge, grounded in the thought of the Bible, was both
confirmed and sustained by a depth of speculative
thinking. The synthesis devised by Saint Augustine
remained for centuries the most exalted form of
philosophical and theological speculation known to the
West. Reinforced by his personal story and sustained by a
wonderful
holiness of life, he could also introduce into his works
a range of material which, drawing on experience, was a
prelude to future developments in different currents of
philosophy.
41. The ways in which the
Fathers of East and West engaged the philosophical
schools were, therefore, quite different. This does not
mean that they identified the content of their message
with the systems to which they referred. Consider
Tertullian's question: What does Athens have in
common with Jerusalem? The Academy with the
Church?.(40) This clearly indicates the critical
consciousness with which Christian thinkers from the
first confronted the problem of the relationship between
faith and philosophy, viewing it comprehensively with
both its positive aspects and its limitations. They were
not naive thinkers. Precisely because they were intense
in living faith's content they were able to reach the
deepest forms of speculation. It is therefore
minimalizing and mistaken to restrict their work simply
to the transposition of the truths of faith into
philosophical categories. They did much more. In fact
they succeeded in disclosing completely all that remained
implicit and preliminary in the thinking of the great
philosophers of antiquity.(41) As I have noted, theirs
was the task of showing how reason, freed from external
constraints, could find its way out of the blind alley of
myth and open itself to the transcendent in a more
appropriate way. Purified and rightly tuned, therefore,
reason could rise to the higher planes of thought,
providing a solid foundation for the perception of being,
of the transcendent and of the absolute.
It is here that we see the
originality of what the Fathers accomplished. They fully
welcomed reason which was open to the absolute, and they
infused it with the richness drawn from Revelation. This
was more than a meeting of cultures, with one culture
perhaps succumbing to the fascination of the other. It
happened rather in the depths of human souls, and it was
a meeting of creature and Creator. Surpassing the goal
towards which it unwittingly tended by dint of its
nature, reason attained the supreme good and ultimate
truth in the person of the Word made flesh. Faced with
the various philosophies, the Fathers were not afraid to
acknowledge those elements in them that were consonant
with Revelation and those that were not. Recognition of
the points of convergence did not blind them to the
points of divergence.
42. In Scholastic theology, the
role of philosophically trained reason becomes even more
conspicuous under the impulse of Saint Anselm's
interpretation of the intellectus fidei. For the saintly
Archbishop of Canterbury the priority of faith is not in
competition with the search which is proper to reason.
Reason in fact is not asked to pass judgement on the
contents of faith, something of which it would be
incapable, since this is not its function. Its function
is rather to find meaning, to discover explanations which
might allow everyone to come to a certain understanding
of the contents of faith. Saint Anselm underscores the
fact that the intellect must seek that which it loves:
the more it loves, the more it desires to know. Whoever
lives for the truth
is reaching for a form of knowledge which is fired more
and more with love for what it knows, while having to
admit that it has not yet attained what it desires:
To see you was I conceived; and I have yet to
conceive that for which I was conceived (Ad te videndum
factus sum; et nondum feci propter quod factus
sum).(42) The desire for truth, therefore, spurs
reason always to go further; indeed, it is as if reason
were overwhelmed to see that it can always go beyond what
it has already achieved. It is at this point, though,
that reason can learn where its path will lead in the
end: I think that whoever investigates something
incomprehensible should be satisfied if, by way of
reasoning, he reaches a quite certain perception of its
reality, even if his
intellect cannot penetrate its mode of being... But is
there anything so incomprehensible and ineffable as that
which is above all things? Therefore, if that which until
now has been a matter of debate concerning the highest
essence has been established on the basis of due
reasoning, then the foundation of one's certainty is not
shaken in the least if the intellect cannot penetrate it
in a way that allows clear formulation. If prior thought
has concluded rationally that one cannot comprehend
(rationabiliter comprehendit incomprehensibile esse) how
supernal wisdom knows its own accomplishments..., who
then will explain how this same wisdom, of which the
human being can know nothing or next to nothing, is to be
known and expressed?.(43)
The fundamental harmony between
the knowledge of faith and the knowledge of philosophy is
once again confirmed. Faith asks that its object be
understood with the help of reason; and at the summit of
its searching reason acknowledges that it cannot do
without what faith presents.
The enduring originality of the
thought of Saint Thomas Aquinas
43. A quite special place in
this long development belongs to Saint Thomas, not only
because of what he taught but also because of the
dialogue which he undertook with the Arab and Jewish
thought of his time. In an age when Christian thinkers
were rediscovering the treasures of ancient philosophy,
and more particularly of Aristotle, Thomas had the great
merit of giving pride of place to the harmony which
exists between faith and reason. Both the light of reason
and the light of faith come from God, he argued; hence
there can be no contradiction between them.(44)
More radically, Thomas
recognized that nature, philosophy's proper concern,
could contribute to the understanding of divine
Revelation. Faith therefore has no fear of reason, but
seeks it out and has trust in it. Just as grace builds on
nature and brings it to fulfilment,(45) so faith builds
upon and perfects reason. Illumined by faith, reason is
set free from the fragility and limitations deriving from
the disobedience of sin and finds the strength required
to rise to the knowledge of the Triune God. Although he
made much of the supernatural character of faith, the
Angelic Doctor did not overlook the importance of its
reasonableness; indeed he was able to plumb the depths
and explain the meaning of this reasonableness. Faith is
in a sense an exercise of
thought; and human reason is neither annulled nor
debased in assenting to the contents of faith, which are
in any case attained by way of free and informed
choice.(46)
This is why the Church has been
justified in consistently proposing Saint Thomas as a
master of thought and a model of the right way to do
theology. In this connection, I would recall what my
Predecessor, the Servant of God Paul VI, wrote on the
occasion of the seventh centenary of the death of the
Angelic Doctor: Without doubt, Thomas possessed
supremely the courage of the truth, a freedom of spirit
in confronting new problems, the intellectual honesty of
those who allow Christianity to be contaminated neither
by secular philosophy nor by a prejudiced rejection of
it. He passed therefore into the history of Christian
thought as a pioneer of the new path of philosophy and
universal culture. The key point and almost the kernel of
the solution which, with all the brilliance of his
prophetic intuition, he gave to the new encounter of
faith and reason was a reconciliation between the
secularity of the world and the radicality of the Gospel,
thus avoiding the unnatural tendency to negate the world
and its values while at the same time keeping faith with
the supreme and inexorable demands of the supernatural
order.(47)
44. Another of the great
insights of Saint Thomas was his perception of the role
of the Holy Spirit in the process by which knowledge
matures into wisdom. From the first pages of his Summa
Theologiae,(48) Aquinas was keen to show the primacy of
the wisdom which is the gift of the Holy Spirit and which
opens the way to a knowledge of divine realities. His
theology allows us to understand what is distinctive of
wisdom in its close link with faith and knowledge of the
divine. This wisdom comes to know by way of
connaturality; it presupposes faith and eventually
formulates its right judgement on the basis of the truth
of faith itself: The wisdom named among the gifts
of the Holy Spirit is distinct from the wisdom found
among the intellectual
virtues. This second wisdom is acquired through study,
but the first 'comes from on high', as Saint James puts
it. This also distinguishes it from faith, since faith
accepts divine truth as it is. But the gift of wisdom
enables judgement according to divine truth.(49)
Yet the priority accorded this
wisdom does not lead the Angelic Doctor to overlook the
presence of two other complementary forms of
wisdomphilosophical wisdom, which is based upon the
capacity of the intellect, for all its natural
limitations, to explore reality, and theological wisdom,
which is based upon Revelation and which explores the
contents of faith, entering the very mystery of God.
Profoundly convinced that
whatever its source, truth is of the Holy
Spirit (omne verum a quocumque dicatur a Spiritu
Sancto est) (50) Saint Thomas was impartial in his love
of truth. He sought truth wherever it might be found and
gave consummate demonstration of its universality. In
him, the Church's Magisterium has seen and recognized the
passion for truth; and, precisely because it stays
consistently within the horizon of universal, objective
and transcendent truth, his thought scales heights
unthinkable to human intelligence.(51) Rightly,
then, he may be called an apostle of the
truth.(52) Looking unreservedly to truth, the
realism of Thomas could recognize the objectivity of
truth and produce not merely a philosophy of what
seems to be but a philosophy of what
is.
The drama of the separation of
faith and reason
45. With the rise of the first
universities, theology came more directly into contact
with other forms of learning and scientific research.
Although they insisted upon the organic link between
theology and philosophy, Saint Albert the Great and Saint
Thomas were the first to recognize the autonomy which
philosophy and the sciences needed if they were to
perform well in their respective fields of research. From
the late Medieval period onwards, however, the legitimate
distinction between the two forms of learning became more
and more a fateful separation. As a result of the
exaggerated rationalism of certain thinkers, positions
grew more radical and there emerged eventually a
philosophy which was separate from and absolutely
independent of the
contents of faith. Another of the many consequences of
this separation was an ever deeper mistrust with regard
to reason itself. In a spirit both sceptical and
agnostic, some began to voice a general mistrust, which
led some to focus more on faith and others to deny its
rationality altogether. In short, what for Patristic and
Medieval thought was in both theory and practice a
profound unity, producing knowledge capable of reaching
the highest forms of speculation, was destroyed by
systems which espoused the cause of rational knowledge
sundered from faith and meant to take the place of faith.
46. The more influential of
these radical positions are well known and high in
profile, especially in the history of the West. It is not
too much to claim that the development of a good part of
modern philosophy has seen it move further and further
away from Christian Revelation, to the point of setting
itself quite explicitly in opposition. This process
reached its apogee in the last century. Some
representatives of idealism sought in various ways to
transform faith and its contents, even the mystery of the
Death and Resurrection of Jesus, into dialectical
structures which could be grasped by reason. Opposed to
this kind of thinking were various forms of atheistic
humanism, expressed in philosophical terms, which
regarded faith as alienating and damaging to the
development of a full rationality. They did not hesitate
to present themselves as new religions serving as a basis
for projects which, on the political and social plane,
gave rise to totalitarian systems which have been
disastrous for humanity.
In the field of scientific
research, a positivistic mentality took hold which not
only abandoned the Christian vision of the world, but
more especially rejected every appeal to a metaphysical
or moral vision. It follows that certain scientists,
lacking any ethical point of reference, are in danger of
putting at the centre of their concerns something other
than the human person and the entirety of the person's
life. Further still, some of these, sensing the
opportunities of technological progress, seem to succumb
not only to a market-based logic, but also to the
temptation of a quasi-divine power over nature and even
over the human being.
As a result of the crisis of
rationalism, what has appeared finally is nihilism. As a
philosophy of nothingness, it has a certain attraction
for people of our time. Its adherents claim that the
search is an end in itself, without any hope or
possibility of ever attaining the goal of truth. In the
nihilist interpretation, life is no more than an occasion
for sensations and experiences in which the ephemeral has
pride of place. Nihilism is at the root of the widespread
mentality which claims that a definitive commitment
should no longer be made, because everything is fleeting
and provisional.
47. It should also be borne in
mind that the role of philosophy itself has changed in
modern culture. From universal wisdom and learning, it
has been gradually reduced to one of the many fields of
human knowing; indeed in some ways it has been consigned
to a wholly marginal role. Other forms of rationality
have acquired an ever higher profile, making
philosophical learning appear all the more peripheral.
These forms of rationality are directed not towards the
contemplation of truth and the search for the ultimate
goal and meaning of life; but instead, as
instrumental reason, they are
directedactually or potentiallytowards the
promotion of utilitarian ends, towards enjoyment or
power.
In my first Encyclical Letter I
stressed the danger of absolutizing such an approach when
I wrote: The man of today seems ever to be under
threat from what he produces, that is to say from the
result of the work of his hands and, even more so, of the
work of his intellect and the tendencies of his will. All
too soon, and often in an unforeseeable way, what this
manifold activity of man yields is not only subject to
'alienation', in the sense that it is simply taken away
from the person who produces it, but rather it turns
against man himself, at least in part, through the
indirect consequences of its effects returning on
himself. It is or can be directed against him. This seems
to make up the main chapter of the drama of present-day
human existence in its broadest and
universal dimension. Man therefore lives increasingly in
fear. He is afraid of what he producesnot all of
it, of course, or even most of it, but part of it and
precisely that part that contains a special share of his
genius and initiativecan radically turn against
himself.(53)
In the wake of these cultural
shifts, some philosophers have abandoned the search for
truth in itself and made their sole aim the attainment of
a subjective certainty or a pragmatic sense of utility.
This in turn has obscured the true dignity of reason,
which is no longer equipped to know the truth and to seek
the absolute.
48. This rapid survey of the
history of philosophy, then, reveals a growing separation
between faith and philosophical reason. Yet closer
scrutiny shows that even in the philosophical thinking of
those who helped drive faith and reason further apart
there are found at times precious and seminal insights
which, if pursued and developed with mind and heart
rightly tuned, can lead to the discovery of truth's way.
Such insights are found, for instance, in penetrating
analyses of perception and experience, of the imaginary
and the unconscious, of personhood and intersubjectivity,
of freedom and values, of time and history. The theme of
death as well can become for all thinkers an incisive
appeal to seek within themselves the true meaning of
their own life. But this does not mean that the link
between faith and reason as it now stands does not need
to be carefully examined, because each without the other
is impoverished and enfeebled. Deprived of what
Revelation offers, reason has taken side-tracks which
expose it to the danger of losing sight of its final
goal. Deprived of reason, faith has stressed feeling and
experience, and so run the risk of no longer being a
universal proposition. It is an illusion to think that
faith, tied to weak reasoning, might be more penetrating;
on the contrary, faith then runs the grave risk of
withering into myth or superstition. By the same token,
reason which is unrelated to an adult faith is not
prompted to turn its gaze to the newness and radicality
of being.
This is why I make this strong
and insistent appealnot, I trust,
untimelythat faith and philosophy recover the
profound unity which allows them to stand in harmony with
their nature without compromising their mutual autonomy.
The parrhesia of faith must be matched by the boldness of
reason.

|